Tag Archives: mathematics

Did Aboriginal Australians predict solar eclipses?

“Mathematics has been gatekept by the West and defined to exclude entire cultures” declares Professor Rowena Ball of the Australian National University, who wants mathematics to be “decolonised”. In one sense she is right, mathematics is indeed “a universal human phenomenon” that transcends individual cultures. But she is wrong to suppose that anyone disagrees; she is wrong to claim that there are people who think of mathematics as having “an exclusively European and British provenance” and want it to remain that way. Rebutting a strawman serves only to signal one’s superior attitudes.

Professor Ball claims that “Almost all mathematics that students have ever come across is European-based”, and yet “algebra” is an Arabic word and so is “algorithm”. Foundational concepts such as the number zero and negative numbers originated in the Middle East, India and China before being adopted by Europeans. The mathematics now taught to schoolchildren in Mumbai and Tokyo is the same as that taught in London.

Being Australian, Ball’s primary concern is to laud the mathematics of indigenous Australians as being of equivalent merit to globally mainstream mathematics, so she wants a “decolonised” curriculum in which “indigenous mathematics” has equal standing.

But how much substance is there to her case? What would actually be taught? Professor Ball’s article gives only one anecdote about signalling with smoke rings, and based on that alone concludes that: “Theory and mathematics in Mithaka society were systematised and taught intergenerationally”.

In a longer, co-authored article, she reviews evidence of mathematics among indigenous Australians prior to Western contact, but finds little beyond an awareness of counting numbers and an ability to divide 18 turtle eggs equally between 3 people. She recounts that they had concepts of North, South, East and West, could travel and trade over long distances, and knew about the relationship between lunar cycles and tides, and had an understanding of the seasons and the weather. And yes, I’m sure that they were indeed expert in the forms of practical knowledge needed to survive in their environment. But there is no indication of a parallel development of mathematics of equal standing to that elsewhere.

The two authors assert: “We also illustrate that mathematics produced by Indigenous People can contribute to the economic and technological development of our current ‘modern’ world”. But nowhere is that actually illustrated. There is no worked example. The suggestion is purely hypothetical. And there is no exposition of what a “decolonised” mathematics curriculum would actually look like.

There is one claim in the article that did seem intriguing:

But Deakin (2010, p. 236) has devised an infallible test for the existence of Indigenous mathematics! This is that there must be ‘an Aboriginal method of predicting eclipse’. To predict an eclipse, one needs clear and accurate understanding of the relationships between the motions of the Sun and Moon. In spite of the challenge, the answer is yes. Hamacher & Norris (2011) report a prediction by Aboriginal people of a solar eclipse that occurred on 22 November 1900, which was described in a letter dated in December 1899.

Predicting solar eclipses is indeed impressive. It requires considerable understanding and long-term record-keeping over many centuries, in order to discern patterns in eclipse occurrences, or it requires some sophisticated mathematics coupled with measuring and recording the locations of the sun and moon to good accuracy. Either is hard to do in a society lacking a written language. (English astronomer Edmond Halley is best known for having predicted the return of a comet and for predicting a solar eclipse over London in 1715, the first secure example of that feat, though it is likely that Babylonian, Chinese, Arabic or Greek astronomers, such as Thales, possibly using something like the Antikythera Mechanism, had done so centuries earlier.)

This geoglyph in the Ku-ring-gai Chase National Park has been interpreted as a record of a solar eclipse, depicting the eclipsed crescent above two figures.

Hence, Professor Ball’s claim of a successful prediction of a solar eclipse is vastly more significant than anything else in her paper. So I looked up the source, a paper by Hamacher & Norris (2011). The evidence is a letter written in December 1899 by a Western woman who says: “We are to witness an eclipse of the sun next month. Strange! all the natives know about it; how, we can’t imagine!”.

Afterwards the same correspondent wrote: “The eclipse came off, to the fear of many of the natives. It was a glorious afternoon; I used smoked glasses, but could see with the naked eye quite distinctly”. But there was no eclipse until a year after the first letter (Nov 1900), not “next month”; the “fear of many of the natives” is incongruous with the suggestion that they had predicted it; and the text of the letters comes from a later compilation in 1903. This is the only piece of evidence given that Aboriginal Australians had developed the ability to predict eclipses; Professor Ball presents nothing else, and nothing from Aboriginals themselves. She gives no account from any Aboriginal about how this is done, and if that’s because she cannot find anyone who could give that account, then doesn’t that count for more than one anecdote that could have been misunderstood or miscommunicated?

That Professor Ball accepts such weak evidence uncritically shows that she is driven by an agenda, not by a fair assessment of the development of mathematics or of the history of indigenous peoples. There is no substance here, no account of what an “indigenous mathematics” curriculum would look like. It does students from indigenous backgrounds no favours to divert then away from global mathematics into “ethnomathematics”. Ironically, it is people like Professor Ball who are telling them that mathematics is “colonised” and European and not for them. This is the wrong message. Mathematics and science are universal, and should be open to everyone, and we should not be dividing universal enterprises into silos with ethnic labels attached.

This piece was written for the Heterodox Academy STEM Substack and is repoduced here.

The unity of maths and physics revisited

scientism A major part of scientism is the idea that maths and logic are not distinct from science, but rather that they arise from the same fundamental root — they are all attempts to find descriptions of the world around us. The axioms of maths and logic are thus equivalent to the laws of physics, being statements of deep regularities of how the world behaves that enable us to describe and model the world.

My article advocating that mathematics is a part of science was recently posted on Scientia Salon. This was followed by an article by Massimo Pigliucci which took the opposite line and criticised the return of “radical empiricism”.

In response I wrote about the roots of empiricism, defending the radical empiricism that Pigliucci rejects. That post was getting rather long, so I have hived off parts into this post where I return to the distinction between mathematics and science. This is essentially a third part to my above two posts, countering various criticisms made on Scientia Salon.

To summarise the above arguments in two sentences, my critics were saying: “Well no, mathematics is anything but studying physical objects. It is the study of abstract concepts”, whereas I was saying, “Yes, mathematics is the study of abstract concepts, abstract concepts that are about the behaviour of the physical world”.

I have argued that maths and logic and science are all part of the same ensemble, being ideas adopted to model the world. We do that modelling by looking for regularities in the way the world works, and we abstract those into concepts that we call “laws of physics” or “axioms of maths” or of logic. Thus axioms of maths and logic are just as much empirical statements about the behaviour of the world as laws of physics. In part one I discussed other possible origins of mathematical axioms, while in part two I discussed the fundamental basis of empirical enquiry.

That leaves several possible differences between maths and science, which I address here: Continue reading

The roots of empiricism: Hume’s fork, and the divide between knowledge “by observation” and “by reason”

Scientia Salon recently published my article advocating that mathematics is best regarded as a part of science. In reply to “scientism week”, Massimo Pigliucci wrote an article criticising “the return of radical empiricism”. The collision of “scientism week” with “anti-scientism week” generated a lot of energy and comments!

Massimo Pigliucci’s article is well worth reading, being a clear exposition of the relevant ideas. He traces the issues back to Hume’s famous fork, in which Hume declares that:

All the objects of human reason or enquiry may naturally be divided into two kinds, to wit, Relations of Ideas, and Matters of fact and real existence.

hume

The “relations of ideas” category is taken to include mathematics and logic, where knowledge is “discoverable by the mere operation of thought”, while the “matters of fact” category contains science, where knowledge derives from empirical data.

Kant rejected Hume’s empiricism and sought to establish the primacy of reason. He adopted the term “a priori” for knowledge that does not derive from experience, in contrast toa posteriori” knowledge which does. A related concept is that of “analytic” statements, which follow from the definitions of the terms, contrasting with “synthetic” statements that describe how the world is.

This notion of a fundamental epistemological divide holds today, and is at the heart of resistance to the idea that mathematics, logic and science are a unified whole.

In reading Pigliucci’s article I agree with much of what he says, but, to me, he seems to miss the main arguments for the essential unity of the different domains of knowledge. I will thus outline how I see the roots of empiricism, and then consider the supposed divide between knowledge “from reasoning” versus knowledge “from observation”. Continue reading

Defending scientism: mathematics is a part of science

While the term “scientism” is often a rebuke to those considered to be overstepping the proper boundaries of science, plenty of scientists will plead guilty to the charge so long as they get a say in how the term is defined. The “scientism” that I defend is the claim that, as far as we can tell, all human knowledge is empirical, deriving from empirical contact with reality. Further, that empirical reality seems, as far as we can tell, to be a unified whole, and thus our knowledge of reality is also unified across different subject areas so that transitions between subjects are seamless.

What we call “science” is the set of methods that we have found, empirically, to be the best for gaining knowledge about the universe, and the same toolkit and the same basic ideas about evidence work in all subject areas. Thus there are no “other ways of knowing”, no demarcation lines across which science cannot tread, no “non-overlapping magisteria”.

A related but different stance is expounded by philosopher Massimo Pigliucci in his critique of scientism [1]. Pigliucci instead prefers the umbrella term “scientia”, which includes “science, philosophy, mathematics and logic”. This sees mathematics and logic as epistemologically distinct from science. Indeed Pigliucci has remarked:

it should be uncontroversial (although it actually isn’t) that the kind of attention to empirical evidence, theory construction, and the relation between the two that characterizes science is “distinctive enough” … to allow us to meaningfully speak of an activity that we call science as sufficiently distinct from … mathematics.

Mathematics is a huge area of knowledge where science has absolutely nothing to say, zip …” [2]

In this piece I argue that mathematics is a part of science. I should clarify that I am taking a broad interpretation of science. Nobody who defends scientism envisages science narrowly, as limited only to what is done in university science departments. Rather, science is conceived broadly as our best attempt to make sense of the empirical evidence we have about the world around us. The “scientific method” is not an axiomatic assumption of science, rather it is itself the product of science, of trying to figure out the world, and is now adopted because it has been found to work. Continue reading

What does “existence” mean?

During a recent online discussion I discovered, somewhat to my surprise, that there is no general agreement on what the word “exist” means. Everyone has an intuitive understanding of it but when it comes to an explicit definition of the word there is no consensus, and indeed philosophers have written a vast literature on the topic of ontology, or what exists.

Dictionaries don’t really help; for example Oxford Dictionaries gives a nicely circular set of definitions:

Exist: 1. have objective reality or being
Reality: 1. the state of things as they actually exist
Being: 1. existence.

Of course physicists have a perfectly good operational definition: something exists if it is capable of making a detector go ping. Try arguing that, however, and you’re immediately accused of materialism, physicalism, scientism, being blind to possibilities beyond a very narrow world-view, and a host of similar sins (I plead guilty to at least the first three). Continue reading

Disagreeing (partially) with Sean Carroll about what is science

Sean Carroll talks a lot of sense on the nature of science, and in a recent post gave a definition of “science” that focuses on the methods and attitudes of science. He wrote:

Science consists of the following three-part process:
1. Think of every possible way the world could be. Label each way an “hypothesis”.
2. Look at how the world actually is. Call what you see “data” (or “evidence”).
3. Where possible, choose the hypothesis that provides the best fit to the data.

It’s a good operational definition, separating a scientific attitude from a pseudo-scientific or religious attitude, although the process needs to be iterative, with the hypothesis of step 3 then being tested against new data; and I would add in Feynman’s maxim: try hard to see whether you are fooling yourself, remembering that yourself is the easiest person to fool.

Later in the article, however, I start disagreeing with Carroll about what is and isn’t science. He says: Continue reading

Scientism and questions science cannot answer

“Scientism” is often taken as the claim that science can answer all questions. Of course there are plenty of things that scientists don’t currently know, so the suggestion is, instead, that science could potentially answer all questions, or at least all meaningful questions.

For example the philosopher Julian Baggini says that

“What is disparagingly called scientism insists that, if a question isn’t amenable to scientific solution, it is not a serious question at all.”

Another noted philosopher, Massimo Pigliucci, writes in his book Nonsense on Stilts :

“The term “scientism” encapsulates the intellectual arrogance of some scientists who think that, given enough time and especially financial resources, science will be able to answer whatever meaningful question we may wish to pose …”

I disagree with these definitions (both of course by people critical of scientism), and suggest that scientism is instead the claim that science can answer all questions to which we can know the answer. The point is that there are many questions that are “meaningful”, yet we can never, even in principle, answer them. First let’s distinguish between meaningful and meaningless questions. Continue reading